One thread
we see in this section’s readings is a question: is art free from the political
world, and if not, what is its relationship? In Plato’s Symposium, we saw addressed art’s potential to be a motivating
factor. This, we recognized, can lead to two conclusions: first, art can
motivate us to work towards whatever we find beautiful about it; and second, we
may be manipulated by artworks, and in turn by artists or other agents—we may
face propaganda. The possibility of manipulation may be reduced by
contemplation of an artwork, but even then there is no guarantee that one will
escape without fulfilling some aspect of someone else’s agenda. If art has the
potential to make us the objects of someone else’s will, is it a good thing? I
think the risk is worth taking, especially if we train ourselves to be contemplative and aware when we
approach artworks.
Schiller
viewed art as necessarily involved in politics, since politics itself lacked
the means to achieve its ends. This lack existed due to what Schiller believed
to be politics’ primarily imaginary existence—it could posit new ends, make new
laws, but could not change what people wanted. There is a sense in which
Schiller is simply wrong—many people will obey laws for reasons that have
nothing to do with art, and both tyranny and just government may rely on the
threat of force to ensure adherence to law (desegregation, for example,
required the presence of the national guard). What these conditions imply,
however, is the lack of understanding and desire on the part of the citizen,
which we hope they would generally have. Of course, understanding all laws is beyond us unless we make it
our profession, but a general sense is not outside our grasp. Art, Schiller
suggests, helps us to desire a different world and thereby manifest and use the
motivation to make it that way.
Benjamin
was concerned with the “aura” of art and the effect of art on the viewer; but
to say ‘the viewer’ is misleading, as Benjamin argued that art had moved away
from the realm of individual contemplation and into a ‘mass’ possession,
something divested of its sacred aura turned into a popular plaything. Benjamin
certainly saw the potential for manipulation in film, of the sort we saw in
Plato and can imagine in Schiller. Camera work, especially, delimits our view
into the movie, but if a movie is working properly, we think only about what is
on the screen, not about the fact that it is
on the screen because of a choice, that this is a shot, and that this is
not an aperspectival view of the world. His suggestion that film invites,
indeed causes, distracted attention explains not only many of our problems in
the modern world, but how we can easily be manipulated in ways we do not
understand. That we become used to engaging in only distracted attention is
itself problematic in that it limits our ability to engage contemplatively and
intelligently with the problems of the real world and puts the average member
of ‘the mass’ at the mercy of someone who has those skills—or at least has the
skills to put together a film that manipulates the viewer.
Sontag noted similar issues in his
analysis of photography, particularly of framing and the problem of
non-intervention—in order to be photographing, one must choose not to intervene
in what takes place. Yet the possibility of preparing a shot also exists. The
sheer volume of photos available also diminishes the effect of each one, and as
eras pass, once-seminal, moving photographs become important only historically,
and moving only indirectly or intellectually, but not sentimentally—we gain
layers of distance. This problem makes photography self-destruct; it cannot
preserve what makes it special and evocative, it is claimed. This is not, I
think, true as an extreme; we have seen that photos still do affect people. As
far as relevance goes, this, too, is true, and we can see the same issue at
stake in the adjustment required for
one to really enjoy many older works of literature, that had different horizons
of expectations, and even, I would argue, for one to enjoy older paintings,
like the unrealistic and somewhat bland paintings that adorn so many religious
sites throughout history. Each of these is made more powerful by understanding
and contextual awareness; each effect diminishes with the distance between us
and it.
Not least among these, Adorno recognized
the originally ritual function of art and its role as a sacred object, and
discussed art as a kind of ‘negative’ in the sense of photo negativity. The
demystification of the artwork via knowledge about it (and perhaps rules of
taste, or something similar—a point I must investigate) allows us to justify
claims about its artistry. Art is dependent on the world, but the question
arises: if art is a negative, does not reality depend on art? To me this
suggests the degree to which we shape our world by contemplative fictions, in
the intellectual and psychological realm, and the way in which we live
according to principles and constructs that are identifiable—even if they are
merely a macroscopic picture of what can be defined more mechanically and
perhaps without account of agency at a lower level. Art is, at all accounts,
tied into reality and truth, but in a way that suggests it both produces
interpretation and is itself, of course, produced. Whether or not its
interpretation is truthful, or truth-conducive, at any rate, or not is a
question all of these authors raise. Another is whether art might not be
something to the side of truth—related to it, but not limited to truth or
untruth at all.
No comments:
Post a Comment