Thursday, November 13, 2014

Nehamas, Kant, and what, exactly, we are interpreting

Nehamas’ concept of a ‘postulated author’ clearly articulates a methodological necessity that I have always instinctively believed to be true of reading. It is also applicable to any field. Authors create works of art because they find there to be something fulfilling or meaningful about doing it, but literary texts in particular cannot escape from meaning-laden-ness simply by virtue of their use of language. Poststructuralists argue that each reader ‘produces’ or creates their own reading of a text as a subject, bringing to bear their own knowledge on each text that they read. A good reading, however, does not simply ignore the author’s intent, and in this I find Nehamas’ position slightly more optimistic than the more realistic approach a theorist like Derrida takes, which buries notions of ‘good reading’ deep inside of an explanation of how reading works whether done well or poorly. Nehamas, however, advocates for a kind of reading more aligned with understanding a text than merely processing it and ‘producing’ it. He suggests that we should interpret texts not simply as they could be interpreted through the variety of connotations attached to a word, but as we have reason to believe the author could reasonably have meant them to be interpreted. For that reason, he proposes a postulated author, differentiating between the author as the one who gives the work meaning in the reader’s mind, and the writer as the actual historical figure. While information about the writer may contribute to our understanding of the author, we are necessarily limited by not being that person—there is only so much about them and their intentions that we can know.
However, an ideal interpretation would encompass all the possible facets of a text—and so, while Nehamas does not advocate making interpretations that are devoid of context (not that I believe Derrida does, either), he does recognize that meaning may arise based on historical developments subsequent to the writer’s initial creation. Personal significance may be added into the reader’s experience, so that different parts are salient because they remind the reader of some personal event. But a work may gain meaning in other ways; some texts, for example, may demonstrate something about feminism precisely for the ways in which they leave it out; ancient texts may reflect conceptions of the ‘other’ that we have now problematized, and may thus teach us how we have moved on from a certain point. Or, Sophocles, an example Nehamas uses, may have been anticipated Freudian preoccupations in Oedipus. But we would not say that Sophocles was a Freudian; we would say that both Sophocles and Freud picked up on the same sorts of interests, and that Freud elaborated on them in a different way than Sophocles, and has since become more emblematic, in part thanks to his co-opting of Oedipus and Sophocles’ genius.

Kant introduces genius to explain how art arises. The genius is a conduit for meaning and for beautiful things to come into being. I think this makes a certain amount of sense when we consider an issue like the focus both Sophocles and Freud lavished on ‘illicit’ sexual desire. Both are considered with natural human desires, but Sophocles manifested his concern in an artistic way that is often considered a paragon of Greek tragedy. It is precisely because he is able to evoke feeling and thought, because he is able to create something with some aspect of beauty, that he is a ‘genius’; he and Freud share a similar interest, but Freud analyzes his in a (somewhat) rational essay format. Sophocles captures something of nature in his tragedy, as Freud does in his essay, but Sophocles’ is a kind of art. We would be hard pressed, I think, to call Freud’s work ‘art,’ though we might call it clever, or thought-provoking, or weird. It is fully in the realm of ideas; Sophocles blurs the boundary and reaches that special space between thought and feeling, the natural and the created, with which Kant seems (if I have begun to understand him) to associate real art. The difficulty of putting that quality into words is apparent; yet this is an important difference, for while Nehamas’ theory explains our attribution of meaning to different works and offers sound advice for grounding our interpretations of any works, Kant requires us to think about what distinguishes art from any work of thought—a very real distinction that I think might escape our notice in our preoccupation with Nehamas’—not genius, but intelligence. 

No comments:

Post a Comment