“Good
Taste”
Good taste is a specious
concept which, if to be taken as something which exists beyond the nominal, requires
not merely a standard of taste but a normativity based on this rule which would
seem to be able to decisively state whether or not a particular individual makes
good use of the standard or not. Despite the guise of some kind of universality
of an object’s beauty, or ugliness, which seems to allow for such normative
claims to be rendered as meaningful, as noted by Kant, aesthetic judgments are
themselves produced out a “disinterested interest” which occurs in absence of an
appeal to a concept or any other feeling of pleasure derived from it. This
creates an unprejudiced judgment but, in contrast to Hume’s thesis, this lack
of prejudice exists completely separate of the education of the observer of the
art object. This is not to say that an educated taste cannot be applied to an
aesthetic judgment but that it is after the fact and ad hoc. The art object
appealed to the observer’s taste before a requirement of the object to be of “good”
taste entered into the equation (“good” taste here means any sort of normative
claim or standard against which the art object is contrasted – what is
considered using a “critical eye”). The thing appeals to the observer before a concept
is attached to it. The object is simply “this,” and “this thing is beautiful”
or “this thing is ugly” (or some degree thereof) are the immediate judgments
which are made and can then be extrapolated to establish a particular pattern which
we may call an individual’s particular “taste.” This is why is it that even
those critics who are said to have the most refined and sophisticated senses of
taste, due either to a natural talent or education, within their field can
maintain “guilty pleasures” which they know
to be completely outside the realm of “good” taste but nonetheless enjoy as
appealing to their own taste.
Even in light of the
adoption of Hume’s notion that taste, specifically “good taste”, is a composite
of the preferences and predispositions exposited by qualified critics, there
are repeated occurrences of objects which are otherwise un-notable being pleasurable
to a majority of observers even when it is known that the object does not
qualify as being particularly tasteful (this is not an occurrence in which a particular
thing has fallen out of fashion or is anachronistic as Hume himself provides an
account for the changing of taste based in cultural and time contexts, but
regards actual objects seated within their time and place which still fall into
this category). The attractiveness, then, of the application of a sort of
principle of taste is due to the sense of the normative character of aesthetic judgments;
there is some feeling that others should share in the purely subjective judgments
which are made about an art, or aesthetic, object. Further, authority is placed
in those who have the highest degree of exposure and education in particular
domains because there is a sense they are much more qualified to make aesthetic
judgments which would be true if there were, in fact, a real principle or law
of taste which could discern good taste from bad. However, without such a principle,
appeals to critics due to their experience is a sort of surrendering of agency
to another – an attempt to have them inform a subjective judgment by placing it
into a quasi-objective realm – instantiated in something such as a review – where
the merits (e.g. being produced using good technique or effectively making a
certain reference in a clever way) of an aesthetic object render whether the object
is appealing or not almost entirely regardless of subjective experience.
In
the face of this relativistic understanding of taste it is difficult to argue
whether the discernment of taste is a meaningful ability, and arguably, it is
not in of itself. For one to have an understanding of their own preferences is a
desirable quality in both others and oneself but it does not have a meaningful
input, in of itself, into the world because each individual has their own taste
which is only truly curated by them (which is why it can be so exciting to meet
someone who seems to share in the same taste – it is not simply confirmation
but a feeling of finding oneself in another). The discernment of taste, then,
is given meaning through socio-cultural constructs which place certain
individuals as authorities of taste, and more encompassingly, inform not merely
what objects in that particular context are in “good” taste (i.e. in fashion)
but how taste should be conceived of altogether. There is an inter-subjective
agreement brought about by cultural conditioning. This is what causes so much
wonder about individuals who defy these cultural conditions and seem to operate
under an entirely different understanding of the world, at least aesthetically,
as a result. Similarly, these same sort of constraints are what causes
aesthetic objects which transcend multiple socio-cultural contexts (constantly
being regarded as beautiful) to seem so powerful and impressive (it may even
provide further momentum to this transcendent ability and perpetuate the
ability outside of the object’s own power – the wonder that it has made it this
far disposes observers to lift it up so it may go farther).
In
summation, “good” taste is a socially derived concept which exploits an appeal
to authority in attempt to be meaningful. Unfortunately, taste is, in of
itself, a relative trait which differs from each individual to the next and is
only able to find any semblance of uniformity in the conformity to
socio-cultural contexts. However, in closing, this does not mean that tastes do
not have an emotional component. Hume touched on the sentimental component
which informs taste, and this is where taste may find its meaning – not as an
informed, critical appreciation but as a sort of social-emotional bond (at the
very least a very real set of predispositions which could be, though most
likely not fully, evaluated by inquiry into their relations with one another
and in reference to other people). And so, taste may not be meaningful in
law-like way but it may still have meaning as a very real concept which is impactful
upon people.
No comments:
Post a Comment