If good taste is a real thing, it
might easily be confused for a kind of subject-preference chauvinism—‘tastes’
are more than just subjective, they are good
or bad, which implies a sort of
‘correctness’ about them. How could taste be judged good or bad if it is not
objectively validated? Kant offers a compellingly original approach to this
problem: he denies an empirical, objective basis for judgments of taste, and
instead grounds them in a mental state that is, in principle, universally
accessible to all subjects. In that case, people who fail to recognize
something as beautiful are encountering some sort of block that prevents them
from experiencing that mental state. This would in turn lead to them having
‘bad taste,’ particularly if they mistakenly called non-beautiful things
beautiful.
What sorts
of things might constitute blocks? Recalling some previous readings, we might
argue that cultural expectations could prevent us from making an appropriately
tasteful judgment. For example, tribal art may not come across as beautiful to
those unfamiliar with it; there is a certain degree of understanding that needs
to be present for one to judge something beautiful—Kant, I think, recognized
this, and that’s why he placed the experience of beauty somewhere between pure
sensory experience and pure mental reasoning, requiring components of both, but
emphasizing a ‘whole’ that is more than the sum of those parts. Hume agreed
with Kant in certain respects. He did not believe beauty to be objective,
although he recognized that taste was related to sensory ‘organs.’ To Hume, if
taste was solely dependent on the sensory organs, there could be no dispute
about its quality, no standard to which it could be held. But Hume believed
that there was such a thing as good
taste, and only through the combination of reason and sentiment could one make
a judgment commensurate with it. In order to get better taste, one would have
to practice combining these faculties, but that practice could indeed improve
one’s taste. For Hume, like Kant, good taste was a synthesis of faculties
directed towards an object.
So what if people combined their
faculties and were still wrong? And how does one go about combining the mental
and the sensory, or achieving something in between them, anyway? I have no
answer for how one combines these faculties. After all, unlike Hume, I have
learned the hard way that practice does not make perfect—perfect practice makes
perfect. If a person does not know what the source of their ‘block’ is, or why
they do not have good taste, or even that
they lack good taste, they cannot improve it by practice. Still, it stands to
reason that if one is to improve one’s taste, one must improve either the
sensory or the rational component. These improvements might include common
aids, like glasses or hearing aids (if
Kant and Hume are right, those who are color-blind or tone-deaf might well be
incapable of having taste as good as someone else, if good taste is measured by how many ‘beautiful’ or ‘tasteful’
things you can successfully recognize. We might solve this problem by likening
this measurement to two tests scored out of different maximum numbers. The
non-color-blind person has a higher maximum numbers of things they can
recognize as beautiful, while we simply exclude those from the list relating to
the taste of the color-blind person).
Mental improvements, however, are
by far the most common, and generally require the sensory organs. Dickie, who
criticizes the aesthetic sense, lends credence to this suggestion in his
discussion of criticism, in which he suggests that, far from reducing their
appreciation by interacting with greater quantities of knowledge when viewing
objects, critics find more ways of
appreciating them, and may have a deeper
appreciation because of their increased understanding. Examples of such
understanding and its physical component might include recognizing types of
brush strokes, specific chords and progressions in music, literary tropes,
kinds of camera shots or angles, etc. All of these require both mental
knowledge and sensory training—a linkage between knowledge and what is
perceived. The key is to strike a balance—to appreciate an object of art for
itself, and to only allow the technical knowledge and sensory charms of a thing
to add to our amalgamated experience of it. As Kant warns, we can move outside
of the frame of viewing if we judge an object too much on technical merits and
not enough on the experience as a whole; Dickie acknowledges that this is true,
too. Good taste, then, would be the possession of one who could balance knowledge and natural appetites
in order to enter that frame of mind from which we can recognize the beautiful
(or the artistically worthy; for as Dickie points out, aesthetics no longer
views all good art as ‘beautiful’). We have come full circle to Kant. The
question now becomes: can we train people to strike that balance necessary to
make judgments in ‘good taste’?
No comments:
Post a Comment