When I began this unit, I had a much simpler conception of
my answer to the question of whether or not beauty is an objective property or
in the eye of the beholder. Out of our three readings, Kant and Devereaux have
particularly complicated my thinking. My first response was to assert that
beauty could not exist without a subject—it was not objective, but purely a
subjective thing. An experience, really, that was neither right, nor wrong, but
rather depended on all the experiences and natural traits of a person up to the
moment in time at which they would interact with any potentially ‘beautiful’
object. Keeping that in mind, I’d like to examine Kant’s ideas in the Critique of Judgment for a while. From
Kant we learn that taste is “not a cognitive judgment, and so not logical, but
is aesthetic—which means that it is one whose determining ground cannot be other than subjective” (131).
So far, so good—taste is about making a judgment concerning beauty, and it is
subjective, not objective in nature. To discuss the varying kinds of responses
we can have to objects, Kant proposes a tripartite scheme: objects we react to
on a purely sensory level are merely “agreeable”; those which we react to in a
primarily cognitive manner are “good”; and, those that are in between, and
uniquely accessible to humans, are “beautiful” (134). He asserts that
“agreeableness is a significant factor even with irrational animals” whereas
beauty “has purport and significance only for human beings, i.e. for beings at
once animal and rational” (134). Beauty is, therefore, a kind of thing that can
be experienced only by humans, with our peculiar blend of rational and animal
existence, and judgments of beauty are made “apart from any interest” (134)
apart from any interest.
I wonder
about how one can make a judgment of beauty apart from interest. Not only that,
but Kant claims that such judgments, though subjective, are universal: “a
universality which does not rest upon concepts of the Object...is in no way
logical, but aesthetic”; this universality “does not join the predicate of
beauty to the concept of the Object
taken in its entire logical sphere, and yet does extend this predicate over the
whole sphere of judging subjects”
(135). This seems to me to conflict with Deveraux’s explanation of how we
interact with art, which I shall now examine.
Devereaux
focuses on the ‘male gaze,’ which is simply one of many lenses which we apply
to the world. “No vision, not even artistic vision, is neutral vision,” writes
Devereaux; “all vision is colored by the ‘spectacles’ through which we see the
world” (651). Deveraux does not see any possibility for a separation between
observation and interpretation; I am not clear at this point on whether or not
Kant’s idea ‘beauty’ rests in a space amalgamating observation and
interpretation, or free of both in
some way (I take the latter possibility from the notion of ‘disinterested’
judgment). A judgment, after all, implies both examining the thing to be
judged, and making a decision; so it is difficult for me to understand how Kant
thinks one can make a judgment independent of background beliefs. Devereaux, it
seems, disagrees: “Observation is always conditioned by perspective and
expectation,” she says, arguing later that we must view artwork not as “a thing
of beauty and a joy forever” but as part of “the everyday realm of social and
political praxis” (651,59). Furthermore, and in direct contrast to Kant’s talk
of “subjective universality,” Devereaux questions some ideas that I think Kant
believes to hold. She questions whether or not there is a ‘pure’ aesthetic
moment, or if art can speak to something universally apprehensible among human
subjects (659). Perhaps most problematically for Kant’s schema, she denies that
“reading or viewing” art can be “value-neutral,” or “neutral activities” (660).
Both instances of the term ‘neutral’ in relation to art seem to me at least
plausibly to represent that state of ‘disinterest’ that Kant thought must be
reached to make a proper judgment of beauty, and Devereaux seems to reject its
plausibility. I find myself aligning with Deveraux; making a judgment divorced
from background beliefs is not something I see as possible. Nevertheless, my
exploration of Kant has been very brief, and I may have misunderstood what he
is getting at. At any rate, the two seem to agree on our question in its
simplest form, and I take my cue from them: beauty is something subjective,
being felt by the subject, and not an objective property of art, even if evoked
by such objects.
No comments:
Post a Comment