The
concept of representation within artworks is one that goes back to the ancient
world – best known under the term “mimesis,” so dubbed by Plato – and as the
nature of art and artistic works has changed, has been repeatedly called into
question and probed for the veracity of any claim that art does, in fact, refer
– specifically the claim that representation, or reference, is essential to
art. Hans-Georg Gadamer and Benedetto Croce took up the project of revising a
mimetic aesthetic theory in light of contemporary changes in art, and reach
seemingly disparate conclusions, but here it shall be argued that in the
demarcation so clearly set between the two is not such a hindrance to an
informed aesthetic theory, receptive of contemporary and past trends in the
arts, and results in the same, final conclusion, that art to some extent does
refer – if only it does so to itself as Croce argued, or perhaps, as Gadamer
claims, something beyond the work. The meeting ground is in the observer, the
one who experiences the art, and here we see that the interactive
characterization of art as a mental category by Croce finds a familiar in
Gadamer – though it is quite possible neither author would feel that this were
so.
When
“mimesis” is referenced in this paper it is best understood as the classical
definition, representation, and was described by Plato as the essential quality
and function of those artworks which serve no purpose beyond being art (art in
a very conventional sense). Throughout this paper, when we talk about art and
artworks it will be strictly referring to those which are intended to, or seem
to, have no function outside of being art.
What
follows is a sketch of representation as an essential function of art within
the bounds of both Croce’s and Gadamer’s aesthetic theories, with respect to
the original discrepancies that each author draws on this point.
Let
us begin with a brief outline of the work of Croce, specifically highlighting
what are seen as the distinctions between his aesthetics and that of Gadamer.
Croce dismisses the notion of art referring to the outside world; those
references we find in artworks are divorced from art itself, and in our
investigations of them we are not experience the artwork qua art but in some other capacity related to whatever we claim the
referent to be. Art is the “contemplation of feeling,” simply put, and all
things which fall outside that category are some other thing even though we may
argue point at an artwork and claim it still as that thing to which we are
referring, if it is not in the capacity of feeling,
then we are not referring to the thing as art. Croce further posits that art is
its own, particular species of mental activity – not subjugated to any other
activity – and, therefore, any mistaken belief that we may understand art qua anything other than art arises from
the mental activity of art interacting with other mental activities. This means
there is an objective standard for art in so much as anything which is art must
affect or cause this particular mental activity, but there remains an
intersubjective condition which Croce believes is a function of culture which
asserts that context does affect whether something is experienced as art. It
should be noted that Croce then goes further to claim that art is presupposed
by all other things based of its input on the level of sense perception/image
feeling, which is clearly the point most irreconcilable with Gadamer’s account,
however, this incommensurability shall be set aside for the time being to focus
on Gadamer’s account, and the essential nature of representation in art to
follow.
For
the sake of brevity, the main claims of Gadamer’s aesthetics will be enumerated
below as concisely as possible. According to Gadamer, art is characterized as
phenomenological and not the Kantian notion of a disinterested attachment.
However, this experience is, itself, not the focus of aesthetics – as opposed
to Croce who believes this is where the study lies – but it is the aspect of
objective realities which reveal themselves within it (see Gadamer’s
examination of main schools of aesthetics analysis), and therefore, art does,
in fact, represent these in itself. Similar to Croce, Gadamer wishes to remove
the conflict of who is to fill the role of final arbiter from between the
theorist and the creator of art but unlike Croce who removes this conflict of
authority by arguing that the two are doing entirely different mental
activities which may overlap but are incommensurate, Gadamer brings them
together as equal members in the discourse of interpretation which for Gadamer
realizes the artwork. In opposition to Croce, Gadamer believes that art
presupposes cognitive and linguistic realities which are then revealed through
our experience of it (but that this requires study of it in this light and not
as merely Croce’s contemplation of feeling).
With
the disparities between the two theories listed above, it would be most
interesting to see where these two theories meet and the source they both draw
on for qualification – if there is to be one, though I argue there is. Both
these theories discuss art as being representative but in astoundingly
different capacities. What follows is an examination of a link between these
two theories and the role of representation within them.
Within
both of these theories there is an appeal to a cognitive element within the
experience of an artwork. For Croce, the experience of art and its
contemplation is representative only of itself and is a distinct mental
activity, but one informed by the intersubjective component of cultural context
which set criteria for what object will activate this particular mental state.
For Gadamer, art reveals through it a cognitive reality, something is
represented to us which we recognize, given the wealth of knowledge we already
have, and we use our preexisting knowledge to examine the artwork. The
commonality here is the presence of a cognitive component which in neither
theory allows art to be divorced entirely from our other cognitive activities
and knowledge. Even for Croce, who seeks to set art in its own category, art
remains interactive without clearly set borders between it and other mental
activities. To unpack this, we can go one step further, and recognize that
which to both Croce and Gadamer refer is a set of background beliefs (which
includes background knowledge though it is not limited to knowledge in the
conventional sense). For both theories, art is actually presupposed by these
beliefs. After all, that which follows is dependent upon what is given. Even further,
I assert, that the function of these background beliefs acts the same in both
theories, at least initially – prior to the contemplation of the art itself. To
elucidate, in order for any observer to recognize an art object as art it must
conform to their belief about what art is. For Croce this is intersubjectively
defined, but we can understand this as a cultural condition which establishes a
predisposition to view certain objects as art and others as not give one’s
up-brining. For Gadamer, it functions much the same but he does not emphasize
the intersubjectivity as necessary, but rather seems to push an individualistic
approach which holds that the particular set of background beliefs possessed by
an individual will greatly affect whether they view a certain object as art and
how they view it. Gadamer admits, however, that art may affect these
presuppositions, and we, ourselves, can see how even in his theory there is
room for a sort of intersubjective conditioning in the form of conformity to
particular standard promoted by one’s culture. To return to the point at hand,
however, these background beliefs not only cause one to recognize an artwork as art (or dismiss it as
something else) but in both theories affect what a person will see represented
within an artwork. For Croce a person may see a multiplicity of overlaps from
history, literature, science, and so on; or perhaps just recognize it as art
representing art. For Gadamer, a person will be actively engaged in find
“familiar’ things represented within the work or risk the work being
unintelligible and possibly dismissed from the category of art. What is
important here is that for both theories, representation remains essential. A
person must recognize some representation as existing, an ability which is
informed by the background beliefs that person has when viewing an art object,
even if the only representation recognized is that of the art representing
itself, the highly abstract, or supposedly “no-thing” at all.
In
summation, therefore, we find that while it would be foolish to say that both
theories are commensurate, but we can recognize the essential role of
representation within artworks for both theories in reference to our background
beliefs which we hold even in our experience of art. Our background beliefs
inform our ability to recognize art as art by recognizing what is represented
in art that makes it so.
No comments:
Post a Comment