There is a relation between a viewer and an artwork. In my
previous essay, I focused heavily on how the viewer physically or
intellectually represents the artwork themselves; while this is an
indispensable aspect of art, I shall focus this time on what I now better
perceive the question to be: the role of representation inside the created
artwork. No work of art exists that is not a thing, and the question we are
facing is what, precisely, the nature of that thing is, in spite of Gadamer’s
assertion that ‘things’ have been destroyed in this modern world.
How are we to evaluate art that is non-objective? If it is
laden with meaning, but that meaning is hidden within the creator’s mind, what
exactly is the artwork representing? Does its meaning change depending on who
is looking at it? Is the creator’s meaning the ‘true’ meaning? Croce’s approach
was to suggest that a historical contextualization should inform a necessarily
subjective viewing. Each experiencer of art would bring their own previous
experiences to bear on it. Plato, while insisting that painting or poetry were
imitations of imitations, did not reject their ability to bring us to the
truth. Rather, he suggested that philosophy was a better method of getting to the truth, precisely because it draws
attention to itself when it imitates; it makes clear its shortcomings and
insufficiencies in communicating a point, and readers of philosophy are not
expected to read philosophy to experience the ‘need’ for art that Croce
believed we are fulfilling in different ways at different times.
If Gadamer is right about the nature of recognition in
mimesis, however, Plato would have been able to reconcile art with the approach
to (I)dea or truth. In the act of recognizing the essence behind a specific
instance of imitation, one must pick up on the real truth behind it. In the
essay on play, he flat out says that representation is essential to artwork;
several of his examples demonstrate that when we view a play, we are not buying
into the represented character or looking beyond it to the actor, but rather we
are (if participating fully) engaging with an idea or essence. The representation serves to channel us towards
that essence. Plato’s warnings are because of what power representation has; he
knows that we must be intelligent and attentive, or else we may be at worst
deceived, diverted by what is before us, and at least pointed towards a ‘wrong’
meaning. Croce and Gadamer seem less concerned with ‘right’ and ‘wrong,’ since
they allow for subjectivity quite nicely.
So, is representation essential to all forms of artwork, as
Gadamer asserts? Let us see if there is any kind of art that can do without it.
If art’s purpose is to connect us to a truth or an essence, then it certainly
seems to require some way of getting
us to that idea. Gadamer’s concept of art as constructed, built by each subject
as they view it, is a kind of authentic experience, and it leaves no room for
an artwork that gets us to an idea by another route. Croce found that art is
only that which fulfills a need that humans have—but it is a need that seems to
have no outlet other than interacting with representations. Plato’s concern is
not art, but the ideas behind art; even he has to rely on representation, but
he hopes that philosophy employs more straightforward representations.
If we take that to be true, consider the following scenario:
two people view a work of art and identify two different essences as inhering
in the artwork. Must one be wrong? Perhaps more importantly, is it only the
essence the creator intended to represent that is ‘true’ or ‘valid?’ If we turn
to Croce, we will see a sensible guideline: accept things that are not
blatantly foolish or intentionally absurd. It’s impossible for us to know
exactly what someone else genuinely experiences when experiencing an artwork.
But, as has been pointed out, if a person does not react to an artwork, that is
not a failure on the part of the artist; it is a lack of connection between a
viewer and a work itself.
Images are obviously representations. The same is true of
plays. What of music? As Gadamer reminds us, it was Pythagoras who told us that
music represents numerical relations, as in fact every thing can be said to. So
whether we listen to a soaring line of Beethoven or a dark melody in Mahler (or
even silence in John Cage), we are hearing something represented. Architecture
is always carefully considered; the follies constructed for European monarchs
were meant to invoke the grandeur of the past, palaces impose authority on
their visitors, homes create senses of comfort (or wealth, or modernity).
In the final analysis, I find it impossible to divorce art
from representation. Imagine an ‘artist’ who rolls a ball of clay about while
staring blankly at a wall. He then includes it in an exhibition without ever attributing any meaning to it
himself. He does not even think about
it. Leaving aside the implausibility of such a scenario, it seems like viewers
would still make assumptions about it, would still experience some fulfillment
of a need or some connection to a truth or idea. But in this case, that would,
I suppose, be extraneous—seeing nothing in that piece of work would be not a
failure on the viewer’s part, but would be recognizing that such a piece was
constructed with no truths behind it
and no artistic qualities that can be fulfilled. Although I think a viewer
could supply such truth or fulfillment themselves, I wonder if we can truly
classify such an ‘accident’ as art.
No comments:
Post a Comment