Is beauty a real property of objects, or is it simply “in the eye of the
beholder”?
Whether beauty is
a property of objects or is “in the eye of the beholder”, as mentioned earlier,
is more a question about if beauty is an objective property or a subjective
property. I believe that beauty is a subjective experience; however, there seem
to be aspects in the contemplation of beauty that adhere to objective
properties. To effectively argue or support my opinion using the authors we
read I must connect their ideas together, for I think that alone it is
difficult to capture not only the reasons for why beauty is subjective but also
its impact in our modern world. To do this I will highlight some critical
points of each author which tie into the question at hand. First I will begin
by discussing what Richard Wollheim discussed in his essay “Art and its
Objects”. He begins his essay by introducing the “physical-object hypothesis”,
a theory that claims that all works of arts are physical objects. He gives
examples of why this theory is not plausible by explaining that there are works
of art that do not have a “physical” instance of what is truly the work of art,
“For the ordinary explanation of how we come to group copies or performances as
being of this book or of that opera is by reference to something else,
something other than themselves, to which they stand in some special relation.”
(Cahn & Meskin 468). Here Wollheim is explaining how copies of the book Ulysses and performances of the opera Der Rosenkavalier are copies that in
some sense imitate the true idea of the book and opera. Needless to say this
parallels the theory of forms that Plato touches on in his discussion about the
arts and imitation.
Now Wollheim gives
us critical insight into how we interpret art; however, his theories alone will
not answer the question about beauty being a property of objects because not
all objects are works of art, therefore we must expand our conversation beyond
simply the realm of artwork. The feminist writer Mary Devereaux writes about
how in today’s media “male gaze” has dominated the ways in which we view women,
resulting in the degradation of many women and men alike. In discussing the
qualities and consequences of “male gaze” Devereaux gives us a very handy
definition which not only expands us beyond artworks but also ties into the
later Kantian ideas which discuss beauty, “Objectification, as I am using the
term, means no more than to make something the object of my gaze.” (Cahn &
Meskin 656). This allows us to consider beauty beyond the realm of artwork, for
a person can essentially make anything the object of their gaze. I feel many
people carry the belief that artwork is made to be beautiful, which to a degree
is sometimes true; however, now we can consider beauty in other things such as
people. Devereaux continues in her essay to speak of the consequences of “male
gaze” by explaining how it degrades women by exploiting their sexuality which
oppresses them because of their portrayal in media as merely objects of male
gaze.
“Male gaze” is not
simply harmful because of the oppression it causes to women and some men, but
is also a systematized construct which has distorted what true contemplation of
the beautiful should be. If we want to ask what contemplation of the beautiful
looks like, I believe we must look to Kant and his serious consideration of beauty.
Diving right into his “Critique of Judgment” Kant explains that beauty is an
aesthetic claim and that such claims are subjective. This is because claiming
that an object is beautiful gives us no concept of what the object is, and
therefore is a quality that does not belong to the object itself. It is
important to note that beauty is not a feeling itself that is experienced but
is something higher which evokes certain feelings when we see it. In his
critique he says, “Everyone must allow that a judgment on the beautiful which
is tinged with the slightest interest, is very partial and not a pure judgment
of taste.” (Cahn & Meskin 132). He says that if a person wants to make a
pure claim of beauty they must be indifferent to the existence of the object in
question, or else one could say they are biased based on the usefulness of the
object or even the cultural influences they have. This gets us back to “male
gaze” which is a construct that inherently contains interest in determining what
is beautiful in modern media. This gendered gaze dominates media and influences
us culturally so intensely that both men and women participate in male gaze,
and this influences us to make claims about beauty that are tinged with the
usefulness or agreeableness of women. Devereaux explains that “male gaze”
reflects male desires, values, and beliefs; and this shows itself when women
are portrayed as merely objects that serve to further their male counterparts
(which also results in the woman’s subjectivity being belittled). This gaze
extends also to simple paintings of nature because we have gendered it and so
enact “male gaze” on works that do not even contain a human presence.
In conclusion we
find that beauty seems to be a subjective experience that is not a quality that
belongs to objects. For a person to make a pure judgment of beauty they must be
indifferent to the object and cannot generalize to all objects that belong in
the same class (a point which both Kant and Wollheim address in slightly
different examples). If beauty were an objective property of objects it would
inform us of some aspect of what the object is. It is the case, however, that
when experience something that is beautiful we cannot pinpoint just what makes
it beautiful, especially when it evokes intense feelings of awe. There rises an
issue in our modern society where “male gaze” has culturally influenced the way
in which we contemplate beauty which has degrees of interest embedded within
it. It is not necessarily a problem that everyone faces but the mass majority
of people tend to face. There is strong reason to believe beauty is subjective;
however, there are complications which may suggest otherwise. Wollheim
introduces a thought experiment where we consider a work of art without
considering the feelings of the creator or the viewer, and reasonable we can
conclude that artworks are able to express emotions free from human
contemplation (or rather human subjective emotions) and so it could be the case
that beauty, too, can be expressed. Kant also explains that even though we
experience beauty subjectively we discuss it with one another as if what we
consider to be beautiful is universally accepted. We firmly accept an object as
beautiful and find it strange when someone does not agree. What we see then is
that even though beauty seems to be a subjective property there seems to be
something objective working behind the scenes.
No comments:
Post a Comment